Setting Minds at Ease: The Effectiveness of Recent Amendments to the Mental Capacity Act

The PDF version of this entry can be found here.


Setting Minds at Ease: The Effectiveness of Recent Amendments to the Mental Capacity Act

Heng Ming Heuy Monica

INTRODUCTION

In March 2016, Parliament amended the Mental Capacity Act1 (“the Act”) with the purpose of empowering more people to make complex choices about their future, as well as to protect mentally incapacitated persons from (primarily) financial abuse. Two amendments stand out: the introduction of paid professionals into the Lasting Power of Attorney (“LPA”) system, as well as the expansion of the Court’s powers over the appointment of the decision-maker.2 This article evaluates the contribution of these amendments to the furtherance of the purpose of the Act in addition to the applicability of developments surrounding the United Kingdom Mental Capacity Act3 [UK MCA] to Singapore law.

MONETISATION OF THE LPA SYSTEM

The first amendment of note is one that enables singles to appoint professional donees to make decisions related to personal welfare and property on their behalf.4 The purpose of this amendment is to pre-empt the spurt in future planning, as predicted from rising singlehood5 and the prevalence of age-related medical conditions such as dementia.6 It plugs a gap in the legal system by accounting for the needs of persons who do not have family members to be their proxy decision-makers. Additionally, the amendment addresses the growing need for deputies, given that the application rate for LPAs remains low7 – which implies that the Court will still be effectively responsible for making decisions for many Singaporeans in the future, through assigning proxy decision-makers.

A point of contention, however, is when professionals will be deemed to be acting in the individual’s best interests. While it is clear that acting for the donee’s best interests is a fundamental principle upheld by the Act,8 the concept of “best interests” is complex to define and difficult to practise. In particular, the main tension would be between the professional’s judgments of what is good for the individual, as opposed to the individual’s own preferences. To elaborate, the Act prescribes that the decision-maker must consider a variety of factors, including the donee’s past and present preferences. At the same time, he must know the “right thing” to do based on his own evaluation of the individual’s present circumstances.9 Arguably, a professional donee or deputy who has little knowledge about the individual’s preferences is more likely to employ a paternalistic approach towards decision-making. In other words, his own understanding of what is beneficial for the incapacitated individual may override the wishes of the latter.

In particular, this problem is exemplified when the professional appointed has little to no interaction with the individual, and therefore is unfamiliar with their needs, situations, or wishes. A similar problem has unfolded in the United Kingdom, where a trend of low quality mental capacity assessments has emerged. In its 2014 review of the UKMCA, the House of Lords found that health care professionals were often not closely involved with the care of the intellectually-disabled person,10 and as a result, their medical assessments were shallow and done in a slipshod manner that “nowhere near matche[d] the seriousness of the issues at stake”.11 Going back to the local context, it is submitted that a poor understanding of the provisions for determining best interests by the professional donees and deputies will create similar problems in the quality of service provided, as well as the adherence to the principle of best interests in the Act, especially since there is no requirement that the professionals must be involved with the individual.

ENHANCED POWERS OF THE COURT

The second issue concerns the amendments which allow the Court to take pre-emptive action against abuse of the LPA. The amendments allow the Court to (1) quickly suspend the powers of a donee or deputy when criminal investigations are undergoing – without requiring prior applications; and (2) speedily revoke the same LPA powers if there is significant risk of them being abused.12 A “significant risk” would include the conviction of the donee or deputy of offences related to fraud or dishonesty. An important distinction is that the appointment of the donee or deputy could nonetheless be revoked even if the offence he committed was not in relation to the donor.

This is a laudable development in the law regarding mentally incapacitated persons, as it protects the assets of the unsuspecting donor from being dissipated. Its benefit can be illustrated by its application to Chung Khin Chun K,13 a recent case which the Minister of Social and Family Development in fact referred to14 in his proposal of the amendments.15 On the facts of that case, there was a significant risk that the donor’s property would be dissipated because the donee had been charged with the offences of falsification of company receipts and criminal breach of trust of monies belonging to the donor.16 The new amendments would resolve this undesirable situation as firstly, the donor’s assets would be preserved during the course of investigations through an order of suspension per s 36A. Secondly, the LPA could be revoked under s 20 such that the problematic donor could be removed and replaced with one the Court deemed fit. The amendments are thus “sensible precaution[s]” that empower the Court to act on the behalf of the vulnerable, even before abuse occurs.17

A criticism, however, lies in the fact that this safeguard is applied later in the scheme of the LPA than what is preferred. What this means is that these powers of the Court become useful only after the LPA has been approved by the Public Guardian, where in fact it would be more logical to root out potential risks at the application stage through a robust vetting process. As voiced by critics like Member of Parliament Joan Pereira, prevention outweighs cure.18

Here, it is important to recall that the principle of the individual’s autonomy is at the heart of the Act (see s 3(1)). As reiterated by Minister Tan Chuan Jin in his parliamentary speech, to interfere in the application process – i.e. to control who the applicants select as their donee(s) – would contravene this principle and perhaps discourage citizens from even applying for the LPA at all.19 Furthermore, it would compromise the capacity of the Public Guardian in providing objective reports to the Court in the course of investigations.

It is therefore submitted that the greatest opportunity for change occurs at the “intermediate” stage of LPAs, which is the period of time following the clearance of the LPA application prior to the materialisation of abuse. To elaborate, the Office of the Public Guardian may employ supervisory methods such as audits to keep an eye on high-risk cases. The risk level of cases can be determined by a checklist of factors including the value of the assets involved, the identity of the donee (e.g. foreigner or person unrelated to the donor) and the donor’s age (which hints at the likelihood of age-related conditions like dementia arising).20 Further, the United Kingdom’s “first year weighted” approach21 to assessing risk in LPAs can be applied locally: As of 2015, the UK Office of the Public Guardian has moved away from classifying cases according to static risk levels; instead, risk levels are commensurate with the type of deputy involved. For instance, cases with first-year deputies are categorised as high-risk, while cases with professional deputies are generally categorised as low-risk. The former cases are later allocated different risk levels depending on the UK Office of the Public Guardian’s re-evaluation of the cases, using annual reports supplied by the deputies. This approach to risk assessment maximises the allocation of resources to the overseeing of cases, and awards high-risk cases greater attention.

CONCLUSION

In conclusion, the key amendments made to the Act in 2016 are meritorious – enhancing the options for future planning as well as strengthening the protection of the LPA against potential abuse. Nevertheless, there remain practical considerations that Parliament can work on to improve the implementation of the Act. It is envisioned that the Act will be a beacon of hope for Singaporeans seeking security when their mental capacity is lost.


[1] Cap 177A, 2010 Rev Ed Sing

[2] Supra note 1 at s 12 and s 17

[3] Mental Capacity Act 2005 (UK), c 9

[4] Neo Chai Chin, "More decision-making options mooted for mentally-incapacitated" TODAY (7 December 2015) <http://www.todayonline.com/singapore/more-decision-making-options-mooted-mentally-incapacitated> (accessed 30 November 2016)

[5] Charissa Yong, "More young people in Singapore staying single" The Straits Times (11 March 2016) <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/more-young-people-in-singapore-staying-single> (accessed 30 November 2016)

[6] Janice Tai, "One in 10 people over 60 have dementia, new Singapore study claims" The Straits Times (25 March 2015) <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/health/one-in-10-people-over-60-have-dementia-new-singapore-study-claims> (accessed 30 November 2016)

[7] “Out of the adult resident population of three million, only about 0.7 per cent have applied for an LPA thus far.” From Lorna Tan, "Draw up an LPA before it's too late" The Straits Times (23 October 2016) <http://www.straitstimes.com/business/invest/draw-up-an-lpa-before-its-too-late> (accessed 30 November 2016).

[8] s 3(5) and 6 of the Act

[9] BHR and Another v BHS [2013] SGDC 149 at [56]

[10] House of Lords, Select Committee on the Mental Capacity Act 2005, Mental Capacity Act 2005: post-legislative scrutiny (Report of Session 2013-14, 13 March 2014) at para 66

[11] Supra note 9 at para 69

[12] Supra note 1 at s 36A(3)(b)(i) and s 17(3)(b)(i)

[13] Chung Khin Chun K (by her deputy Mok Chiu Ling Hedy) v Yang Yin and others [2015] SGHC 215

[14] Singapore Parliamentary Debates, Official Report (14 March 2016) vol 94 (Tan Chua Jin, Minister for Social and Family Development)

[15] Mental Capacity (Amendment) Bill 2016 (Bill 11 of 2016)

[16] PP v Yang Yin [2015] SGHC 3

[17] Robert Hurling, "Singapore: Mental Capacity Act Amendments", Hyphen Law [2016] <http://www.hyphenlaw.co.uk/site/blog/hyphen-blog/singapore-mental-capacity-act-amendments> (accessed 30 November 2016)

[18] Supra note 13 (Joan Pereira, Member of Parliament for Tanjong Pagar)

[19] Supra note 13

[20] Supra note 13 (Denise Phua Lay Peng, Member of Parliament for Jalan Besar)

[21] Office of the Public Guardian, Fundamental Review of the Supervision of Court Appointed Deputies by the Public Guardian (Report to Parliament, December 2014) at para 77


"The Geeks Shall Inherit the Earth": Two-way Influences amongst Fintech, Finance and Law

Download the PDF version of this entry here.


"The Geeks Shall Inherit the Earth": Two-way Influences amongst Fintech, Finance and Law

Chew Jia Yi Joan

INTRODUCTION

“The geeks shall inherit the earth” is a phrase articulated by a Fintech company in Silicon Valley.1 While the “geeks” behind Fintech may not yet have taken over Singapore, Singapore was recently named as one of the world’s top 2 Fintech hubs.2 Clearly, Fintech will continue to influence local society, in particular its financial industry. This article aims to evaluate the two-way influences amongst Fintech, the financial industry and legal regulation mechanisms, as well as consider plausible future developments to their relationship.

A. Definition of Fintech

Fintech represents the innovative convergence of finance and technology. It can be defined at both the service and industry levels. In terms of a service, it involves the provision of financial services using new technologies, such as mobile phones and the Internet. In terms of industry, it refers to a non-financial business providing services such as payment without collaborating with a company specialising in financial services.3 Some well-known examples of these are Apple Pay and Alibaba’s AliPay.4

B. General Social Impacts

One of the areas in which Fintech is most relevant to the average Singaporean’s life is perhaps digital payments. Across the world, mobile payments alone were expected to grow by 60.8% in 2015, largely due to regulators’ willingness to allow new Fintech companies to operate without a banking license.5 Another important factor for this was new technology allowing for the implementation of novel solutions at far less than what it would have previously cost.6 In addition, the continued recovery of mature economies was also a contributing factor.7 Given the predicted stabilisation of global markets rather than strong growth,8 it is plausible that the rapid growth of Fintech services might slow down, but it is unlikely to stop completely.

On a larger scale, Fintech might be able to help hedge the financial consequences of an aging society, such as through peer-to-peer (P2P) lending services.9 Singapore is unquestionably a rapidly ageing society, with over 25% of the population reaching old age by 2030.10 The exact impact of Fintech on an aging society remains to be seen, but there will probably be some form of impact in future as both these elements are here to stay.11

FINTECH’S INFLUENCE ON THE FINANCIAL INDUSTRY AND ITS REGULATORS

Apart from impacts on society in general, it is likely that Fintech will have a strong influence on the financial services sector. As the legal and financial industries are closely connected, the impact of Fintech on the legal sector cannot be ignored as well. An analysis of such an impact is important given the significance of the financial and legal industries in Singapore—these industries are critical for Singapore to maintain its status as a regional economic and legal hub.12 As the influence of Fintech in the local context might not be completely visible at present, relevant examples from other jurisdictions will also be mentioned.

A. Fintech Services Offered by Banks

Some Fintech services offered by banks can be said to be at odds with some of the core principles traditionally governing banking operations. Firstly, banks have traditionally been proponents of calculated risks, such as their facing the risk of mortgagees being unable to pay back their mortgages in an economic downturn. This is because they have the chance to profit from such risks if their calculations are accurate. However, in the market of certain Fintech services such as digital payments, there is a focus on minimising risk because profitability does not stem from such risks.13 Secondly, building good relationships with customers has always been important in banking, but Fintech services such as digital payments do not place as much emphasis on the quality of relationships with customers. 14 As such, it is plausible that there may be an eventual separation of the banking and Fintech industries.15

However, there are some areas in which the fundamental principles governing Fintech and banking operations have not been in direct conflict. Rather, in these areas, Fintech has merely resulted in a shift in the type of business banks undertake. Such a shift would be beneficial for financial regulators. For instance, in the wake of the 2008 financial crisis, banks have acknowledged the importance of transactions, apart from their traditional risk-taking, as a means of generating profit. The ability of digital payments to facilitate such transactions would complement, rather than hinder, the banks’ developing an ideal transactional framework.16 Indeed, Internet banking has resulted in at least 50% of over-the-counter payments in some Chinese banks.17 Given that it might be harder for banks to check the authenticity of a customer’s over the Internet as compared to looking at the physical person, legal regulations focusing on Know Your Customer (KYC) and Anti-Money Laundering (AML)18 regulations will only continue to grow in importance. Indeed, the Monetary Authority of Singapore (MAS) has recently embarked on a project to create a national KYC utility, and has acknowledged that there might even be a need for more advanced types of KYC guidelines.19

B. Fintech services offered by companies other than banks

As for Fintech services belonging to non-financial companies, there has been a rise of services that threaten the very existence of the formal banking sector. These companies, with their services such as Bitcoin, involve peer-to-peer networks managed by the Internet community.20 This compromises the need for financial institutions in this area. This development also potentially makes it harder for legal regulations, as there are arguably more parties to regulate than in traditional banking. However, at the same time, this obstacle is not insurmountable as some Fintech services leave a permanent financial record of each transaction through usage of blockchains.21 This would be of some comfort to regulators as it would aid in their continuing to play their roles effectively.

Furthermore, Fintech services might also benefit regulators of traditional financial institutions in terms of reducing their workload. The new Fintech companies will be able to help traditional financial institutions achieve some of the outcomes that legal regulators have been aiming to achieve with the financial sector, such as developing Singapore into an international financial centre.22 To do so, legal regulators have to ensure financial institutions cut costs and deliver quality financial services. Fintech companies can help regulators achieve such outcomes through competition. For instance, American Fintech start-up Lending Club’s expenses as a share of its loan balance is about 2%, less than half the equivalent for conventional moneylending services.23 This results in better deals for customers, who are increasingly shifting away from traditional banking platforms. Hence, such competition will force financial institutions to work towards the goals that regulators have been setting for them all along,24 helping regulators in this respect.

RESPONSE OF THE FINANCIAL INDUSTRY AND ITS REGULATORS TO FINTECH

Although the shift towards Fintech has not been a total bed of roses for financial institutions and their regulators, they have tried to keep abreast of developments in this area and ensure their continued relevance.

For instance, banks might actively take steps to hinder the development of Fintech. This is because banks have no clear financial incentive to support Fintech start-ups. On the contrary, some aforementioned aspects of their operations are arguably threatened by Fintech start-ups. Such steps are apparent in countries such as the United Kingdom, where HSBC and Barclays have closed the accounts of some digital currency operators and refused to give them merchant identification for receiving direct debit payments.25

Such pushback from financial institutions leads to a greater role for legal regulation in the financial industry as a whole. For instance, during his term in office, former United Kingdom Chancellor of the Exchequer George Osborne promised legislation to help Fintech firms obtain capital. This included a proposal to force banks who refuse to grant them loans to refer them to alternative sources of funds, such as crowdfunding.26 It is plausible that given the context of both Singapore and the United Kingdom aiming to become Fintech hubs,27 Singapore might also introduce similar regulations to actively aid Fintech start-ups resolve cash flow issues.

An area in which Singaporean regulators are already helping Fintech companies is their navigation of the complex legal landscape. At present, apart from the aforementioned KYC and AML regulations, there are many other regulations that both banks and Fintech start-ups have to deal with in launching their services. Despite such regulations aiming to make Fintech safe for society to utilise, some of them may not have fully caught up with the novel business models that Fintech services employ, which would hinder true innovation in the field.28 In response to this problem, the MAS has recently allowed banks and Fintech start-ups to apply to join a ‘regulatory sandbox’, in which certain legal and regulatory rules will be relaxed to allow for the testing of new Fintech services.29 Companies will then be able to focus on developing their services while only focusing on compliance with the more important regulations which will not be relaxed during the ‘sandbox’ phase, such as some AML rules.30 Should these experiments prove successful, the Fintech services would be applied on a broader scale, upon which they would then comply with all relevant legal regulations. Thus, this scheme will aid both banks and Fintech start-ups to better understand the relevant regulations and comply with them, without stifling their experimentation.

Greater legal regulation may also lead to increased popularity of Fintech services amongst the general population Increased government regulation of the Fintech sector may help to overcome ordinary consumers’ security-related concerns regarding Fintech. For instance, online payment systems, particularly those involving P2P transfers, may be more vulnerable to personal data theft than traditional payment methods.31 It also does not help that there has been a steady rise in scams involving online credit transfers, such as when sellers do not deliver goods after the buyer has paid for them online.32 This comes despite companies such as PayPal helping buyers obtain refunds from errant sellers.33 This indicates a plausible role for greater legal regulation to prevent exploitation of innocent users of Fintech services. With greater regulatory control over the sector, potential Fintech users may have these fears allayed. This would thus aid the growth of the local Fintech customer base.

CONCLUSION

In conclusion, it has been shown that there is a strong influence by Fintech on existing financial institutions and their regulators. Although Fintech has resulted in banks facing more difficulty in certain aspects of their operations, it has arguably benefitted financial regulators in some areas, such as through increasing their relevance. Vice versa, banks and regulators can also hinder or aid the growth of the Fintech sector, though it seems that regulators are playing a greater role in Fintech’s expansion. Indeed, Commentators have suggested that regulators can do even more to aid the shift towards Fintech, such as through facilitating the establishment of courses focusing on digital financial services for students trained in business and Information Technology (IT).34 Although all governments face restricted ability to undertake regulatory commitments,35 this limitation might be particularly pertinent in Singapore where resources are generally scarce. Thus, it would be ideal if regulators could find low-resource ways to better regulate the “geeks” behind the Fintech sector, enabling its growth while increasing protection of users.


[1] Ravi Menon, “A Smart Financial Centre” (Keynote Address delivered at the Global Technology Law Conference, 29 June 2015), online: <www.mas.gov.sg/news-and-publications/speeches-and-monetary-policy-statements/speeches/2015/a-smart-financial-centre.aspx> [Menon, “A Smart Financial Centre”].

[2] Jun Jie Woo, “To be a FinTech Hub, Singapore Needs RegTech”, Today (27 October 2016), online: <todayonline.com>.  

[3] Yonghee Kim, “The Adoption of Mobile Payment Services for “Fintech”” (2016) 11:2 IJAER 1058.

[4] Ibid.

[5] Ross P Buckley & Ignacio Mas, “The Coming of Age of Digital Payments as a Field of Expertise” (2016) 1 U Ill J L Tech & Pol’y 71.

[6]  Ibid at 78.

[7] Ibid at 71.

[8] Interview of Franziska Ohnsorge, Chief Economist, Development Propsects Group, World Bank by Grzegorz Siemionczyk (21 January 2016) at online: <www.worldbank.org/en/news/opinion/2016/01/21/
it-is-not-then-that-the-global-economy-has-returned-to-normal> .

[9] Christopher Chan, “Hedging the Aging Society: Challenges to the Insurance Market and Law in Singapore” (2016) [unpublished, archived at Social Science Research Network Electronic Library] at 13-14.

[10] Ibid at 1.

[11] Chan, supra note 9 at 14.

[12] Sarah Kogan, “Singapore’s Legal Sector: The Fight for Market Share”, The Business Times [of Singapore] (15 February 2015), online: <businesstimes.com.sg> .

[13] Buckley & Mas, supra note 5 at 73.

[14] Ibid at 75.

[15] Ibid at 87.

[16] Ibid at 77.

[17] Weihuan Zhou, Douglas W Arner & Ross P Buckley, “Regulation of Digital Financial Services in China: Last Mover Advantage?” (2015-2016) 8: Tsinghua China L Rev 25 at 35.

[18] Alan Gelb, “Balancing Financial Integrity with Financial Inclusion: the Risk-based Approach to Know Your Customer” (2016) Center for Global Development Policy Paper 74.

[19] Ravi Menon, “Singapore’s Fintech Journey—Where We are, What is Next” (Address at Singapore FinTech Festival—FinTech Conference, 16 November 2016), online: <www.mas.gov.sg/News-and-Publications/Speeches-and-Monetary-Policy-Statements/Speeches/2016/Singapore-FinTech-Journey.aspx>.

[20] Buckley & Mas, supra note 5 at 79. 

[21] Michael Mainelli & Alistair Milne, “The Impact and Potential of Blockchain on the Securities Transaction Lifecycle” (2016) SWIFT Institute Working Paper No 2015-007 at 3.

[22] Monetary Authority of Singapore, “Overview” <www.mas.gov.sg/About-MAS/Overview.aspx> (accessed 28 November 2016).

[23] “The Fintech Revolution”, The Economist (9 May 2015), online: <economist.com> .

[24] Menon, “A Smart Financial Centre”, supra note 1. 

[25] Martin Arnold & Sam Fleming, “Regulation: Banks Count the Risk and Rewards”, Financial Times (November 14, 2014), online: <ft.com> .

[26] Arnold & Fleming, supra note 25.

[27] Ibid.

[28] “Piecemeal Regulation is Hindering US Fintechs”, Business Insider (17 October 2016), online: <businessinsider.com> .

[29] Monetary Authority of Singapore, Media Release, “MAS Issues “Regulatory Sandbox” Guidelines for FinTech Experiments” (16 November 2016), online: MAS Media Releases <www.mas.gov.sg/News-and-Publications/Media-Releases>.

[30] Weilun Soon, “MAS Issues Guidelines for Fintech Regulatory Sandbox”, The Business Times [of Singapore] (16 November 2016), online: <businesstimes.com.sg> .

[31] Jennifer Windh, “Peer-to-peer Payments: Surveying a Rapidly Changing Landscape” (2011) Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta at 17.

[32] Huiwen Ng, “$1m Lost to Online Purchase Scams”, The Straits Times (28 November 2016), online: <straitstimes.com> .

[33] Windh, supra note 31 at 18. 

[34] Buckley & Mas, supra note 5 at 86. 

[35] Joseph E Stiglitz, “The Role of the State in Financial Markets” (Paper delivered at the World Bank Annual Conference on Development Economics, 1993), (1994) Proceedings of the World Bank Annual Conference on Development Economics 19 at 33.


The Case For Removal Of HIV-Related Immigration Restrictions In Singapore

The PDF version of this entry can be found here.


The Case for Removal of HIV-Related Immigration Restrictions in Singapore

Foo Ee Yeong Daniel

INTRODUCTION

In 1998, persons suffering from Acquired Immune Deficiency Syndrome (AIDS) or infected with Human Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV) were explicitly listed as “prohibited immigrant[s]” under s 8(3)(ba) of Singapore’s Immigration Act1 to protect Singapore’s public health in the wake of a global HIV epidemic.2 This manifested in a ban on HIV-positive foreigners from entering the country. While the ban on foreigners on short-term visit passes was quietly lifted in 2015, persons with HIV or AIDS are still prohibited from long-term visits to Singapore – the official reason being that “the public health risk posed by long-stayers is not insignificant”.3 This article aims to study the reasons for s 8(3)(ba) and the existing HIV-related immigration restrictions, and submits that they should be repealed and removed respectively.

THE CASE FOR REMOVAL OF HIV-RELATED IMMIGRATION RESTRICTIONS

A. The restrictions are an outdated model intended for an unpredictable epidemic

It is submitted that the restrictions on HIV-positive immigrants no longer serve their original purpose as a response to an unpredictable epidemic on a global scale. The context in which HIV-positive foreigners were listed as “prohibited immigrants” in 1998 concerned a dramatic increase in the number of HIV infected residents: Singapore had almost 200 reported cases, and more alarmingly, 42 new cases of HIV and AIDS were reported in 1991, vis-à-vis the 61 cases between 1985 and 1990. Against this backdrop of domestic increase in HIV infections was our large number of HIV-positive foreigners: 2,813 foreigners had been tested to be HIV-positive while in Singapore, 80% of whom were work permit holders and applicants.4 The “policy on the repatriation and permanent blacklisting of HIV-positive foreigners”5 was Singapore’s consequent response to that global crisis, as we were perceived to be “particularly vulnerable… [given] people coming into Singapore in far greater numbers, and Singaporeans [travelling] abroad even more frequently”.6

It is submitted that this policy is outmoded. Today, the rate of new HIV cases has generally been constant at about 450 new reported cases each year since 2008.7 The rate of HIV infection is generally maintained unlike in the past; treatment and control measures have made the disease much more predictable, and the heavy response we opted for decades ago is arguably inappropriate given the relatively moderate scale at which HIV spreads today.

Furthermore, immigration restrictions have become a disproportionate response to the severity of HIV, which today has reduced dramatically. The policy against HIV-positive foreigners was recommended when HIV was “new, fatal and no effective treatment was available”;8 HIV was considered a “death sentence”.9 This is no longer the case today as “more than 5,000 Singapore residents [live] with HIV” and there is “effective treatment for the disease”. In fact, HIV-positive persons on antiretroviral therapy may be “successfully virally suppressed” and “not infectious to other people”. In this vein, it is submitted that any prohibition on HIV-positive immigrants despite their non-infectiousness is disproportionate to the alleged “public health risk” they pose.

B. The restrictions are ineffective in reducing the spread of HIV

Increasingly, it is clear that Singapore’s policy against HIV-positive immigrants does not reduce the type of public health risk it purports to.11 Since 97% of HIV contraction in Singapore is through sexual intercourse,12 the main persons at risk are sexual partners of infected persons, who only transmit HIV via certain kinds of sexual behaviour; no health risk is posed to the general public through casual contact. Persons infected with HIV are thus significantly different from persons infected by other contagious diseases that make their very “presence in Singapore dangerous to the community”,13 and should not warrant the same immigration restrictions they do. Most importantly, punitive measures such as immigration restrictions have been proven to be relatively ineffective in preventing transmission, and in fact “may limit the uptake of HIV voluntary testing and hinder adherence to HIV treatment”.14 In this vein, it is submitted that an HIV-positive person should not be banned from long-term stay in Singapore while a person suffering from a different type of sexually transmitted disease is not, since these are all ‘controlled’ diseases that are not effectively reducible by immigration restrictions.

Furthermore, concerns that foreigners (aware or unaware of their HIV status) may (intentionally or unintentionally) spread the disease would generally be well controlled under Singapore’s strict domestic laws against HIV infection.15 In particular, an immigrant who knows he has HIV,16 or for whatever reason does not know he has HIV but has reason to believe that he has or has been exposed to a significant risk of infection, must disclose this risk to his sexual partner before engaging in sexual activity, or be liable to criminal charges as per s 23(2) of the Infectious Diseases Act.17

In any case, the risk of HIV spreading is greatly ameliorated by the availability of anonymous HIV testing, increasing public education about HIV in schools and workplaces,18 guidelines to manage HIV at the workplace, and advancements in public health practices19 – all of which would be readily available to both the HIV-negative populace and HIV-positive immigrants to mutually prevent infection.

In this vein, it is further submitted that the distinction between the public health risk posed by short-term visitors and long-term visitors is arbitrary; the duration of one’s stay is much less a variable of a person’s infectiousness, compared to more important factors such as one’s knowledge, disclosure and treatment of the disease – all of which are generally well regulated in Singapore.

While it is acknowledged that HIV infection rates are still higher than before Singapore implemented its current HIV-related immigration restrictions in 1998, it is submitted that lifting our immigration restrictions would have negligible effect on the current domestic spread of HIV. Firstly, overall HIV infection rates among adults are stabilising worldwide;20 Singapore’s HIV infection rates are not out of the ordinary, and removing HIV-related immigration restrictions would not reasonably lead to an exceptionally large number of HIV-positive foreigners entering Singapore. Secondly, the spread of HIV carried by immigrants may be circumscribed, for instance, by continuing to require mandatory testing for long-term visitors21 and/or subjecting them to the same laws relating to HIV infection as those applying to all Singaporeans.

C. Repealing s 8(3)(ba) would reduce stigma and better satisfy public conscience

It is submitted that removing HIV-related immigration restrictions would better achieve Parliament’s underlying objective to promote inclusiveness and reduce stigma today. When Parliament crafted HIV-related laws, they were concerned with treating patients “humanely and with great compassion” as they and their loved ones undergo “great suffering and social stigma”.22 However, this had to be balanced with “protecting innocent people” from contracting HIV,23 which led to prohibitions on HIV-foreigners from entering the country while HIV-positive Singaporeans remained to seek treatment at home. Noticeably, this by implication seems to unfairly characterise HIV-positive immigrants as a group distinct from “innocent people” in society, even though HIV-positive persons are in many cases victims of circumstance. Given our many health and social support systems, as well as the treatability of HIV that may even render an infected patient ‘risk-free’, the protection of both HIV-positive and negative persons today is not a zero-sum game. It is thus submitted that Parliament’s previous concern about balancing the interests of HIV-positive and negative persons today should be adjusted such that HIV-related immigration restrictions are removed.

Further, Parliament should repeal s 8(3)(ba) as a matter of public conscience. Since the late 20th Century, HIV-positive persons have ranged from married wives infected by their husbands, to children infected perinatally, to blood donees via transfusion, to health care workers via clinical procedures.24 97% of HIV contraction in Singapore is through sexual intercourse, and this is not limited to individuals engaging in high-risk sexual behaviour – often victims have sexual partners’ whose HIV status was either undisclosed or unknown. It therefore seems unjust that the HIV-positive foreigner is labelled a “prohibited immigrant” alongside charges on the public,26 outlaws,27 prostitutes,28 procurers,29 vagrants,30 and persons seeking to overthrow the government by violence31 as our laws should seek treat them with compassion accordingly.

To this end, it is submitted that HIV-positive persons should be allowed to enter Singapore as ‘lawful’ immigrants and stay long-term should they choose to, without being ‘exceptionalised’ and ‘othered’ as a group whose mere presence is a danger to public health – a widespread perception that is taught as untrue, and would be better proven with the removal of s 8(3)(ba). Such a legal reform would enhance the inclusiveness of our whole community, which includes both HIV-positive and negative persons.

CONCLUSION

Removing HIV-related immigration restrictions would not be an unprecedented policy, and Singapore has the benefit of gleaning from the experience of many other countries that have done this. From 2000 to mid-2013, there was a more than 50% reduction in the number of territories with HIV-related travel restrictions – from 96 to 43.32 In particular, the United States had a similar experience to Singapore’s: first applying a blanket ban on HIV-positive foreigners given its large influx of immigrants and the explosion of the AIDS epidemic in the 1980s, before removing the restrictions on short-term travellers in 2006, and eventually removing the ban entirely in 2010 – a process catalysed by vocal opposition from the international community.33 Changing a law typically takes time and effort, and the process requires the community to voice its concerns and what it thinks is right. This article hopes to aid in this respect, as part of former and ongoing efforts by other members of the community to do the same.


[1] Immigration Act (Cap 133, 2008 Rev Ed),

[2] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 69, col 939 (4 September 1998) (The Minister for Home Affairs (Mr Wong Kan Seng)),

[3] The Straits Times, “Ban on entry into Singapore eased for foreigners with HIV”, online: <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/ban-on-entry-into-singapore-eased-for-foreigners-with-hiv>.

[4] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 24 (26 February 1999) (The Senior Minister of State for Health (Dr Aline K. Wong)).

[5] Supra note 3.

[6] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 31 (26 February 1999) (Mr Bernard Chen (West Coast)).

[7] The Straits Times, “455 new cases of HIV reported in Singapore in 2015, most patients got virus through sex”, online: <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/health/455-new-cases-of-hiv-reported-in-singapore-in-2015-most-patients-got-virus-through>.

[8] Supra note 3.

[9] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 31 (26 February 1999) (Mr Bernard Chen (West Coast)).

[10] The Straits Times, “Ban on entry into Singapore eased for foreigners with HIV”, online: <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/ban-on-entry-into-singapore-eased-for-foreigners-with-hiv>.

[11] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 69, col 937 (4 September 1998) (The Minister for Home Affairs (Mr Wong Kan Seng)).

[12] Supra note 7.

[13] s 8(3)(b), Immigration Act (Cap 133, 2008 Rev Ed).

[14] UNAIDS Report 2013, page 92.

[15] ss 22 to 25A of the Infectious Diseases Act (Cap 137, 2003 Rev Ed).

[16] Ibid at s 23(1).

[17] Ibid at ss 23(2).

[18] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 86, col 1969 (11 January 2010) (Mr Khaw Boon Wan).

[19] This is similar to the considerations made by the United States in deciding that HIV infection is no longer a “significant public health risk”, as per the Department of Health and Human Services, “Medical Examination of Aliens – Removal of Human Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV) Infection From Definition of Communicable Disease of Public Health Significance”, online: <https://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/FR-2009-11-02/html/E9-26337.htm>.

[20] AVERT, “Global HIV and AIDS Statistics”, online: <http://www.avert.org/global-hiv-and-aids-statistics>.

[21] Immigration & Checkpoints Authority, “Medical Examination for Successful Applicants of Employment Pass, Long-Term Immigration Pass and Permanent Residence”, online: <https://www.ica.gov.sg/news_details.aspx?nid=4497>.

[22] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 29 (26 February 1999) (The Senior Minister of State for Health (Dr Aline K. Wong)).

[23] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 34 (26 February 1999) (Dr Lily Neo (Kreta Ayer-Tanglin)).

[24] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 70, col 25 (26 February 1999) (The Senior Minister of State for Health (Dr Aline K. Wong)).

[25] The Straits Times, “455 new cases of HIV reported in Singapore in 2015, most patients got virus through sex”, online: <http://www.straitstimes.com/singapore/health/455-new-cases-of-hiv-reported-in-singapore-in-2015-most-patients-got-virus-through>.

[26]Immigration Act (Cap 133, 2008 Rev Ed), s 8(3)(a).

[27]Ibid at s 8(3)(d).

[28] Ibid at s 8(3)(e).

[29] Ibid at s 8(3)(f).

[30] Ibid at s 8(3)(g).

[31] Ibid at s 8(3)(i).

[32] Global Report UNAIDS report on the global AIDS epidemic 2013, page 92, online: <http://www.unaids.org/sites/default/files/media_asset/UNAIDS_Global_Report_2013_en_1.pdf>.

[33] National Institutes of Health, United States National Library of Medicine, “The Impact of Removing the Immigration Ban on HIV-Infected Persons”, online: <https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3263303/>.


The Nature and Scope of the Right to Vote in Singapore

Download the PDF version of this entry here.


The Nature and Scope of the Right to Vote in Singapore

Feng Zheyi

Democracy (from the Greek dêmos “people” and krátos “rule”) is premised on popular vote. Government decisions are made by the people themselves, their elected representatives, their nominees, or some combination of the above. The right of the people to vote, either in referendums or in elections, are hence fundamental and central to any democracy – democracy without voting is simply a contradiction in terms.1

One might expect this centrally important right to be enshrined in constitutional documents, and not be subject to much confusion. However, in Singapore, the precise nature and the scope of citizens’ right to vote remains murky, a rather unsatisfactory state of affairs. It is suggested that the inclusion (by constitutional amendment) of an explicit constitutional right to vote would reduce much of the surrounding uncertainty.

THE STATUS QUO

The right to vote is not explicitly recognised in the Constitution, but has been explicitly declared by Minister for Law Mr K Shanmugam as an implied constitutional right.2 More recently, the Court of Appeal in Vellama d/o Marie Muthu v Attorney-General3 opined (in dicta) that voters in a constituency are “entitled to have a Member representing and speaking for them in Parliament”,4 somewhat mirroring the aforementioned declarations by the Minister in Parliament.

The right to vote is further explicitly detailed in the Parliamentary Elections Act [PEA],5 which provides that “any person who [is qualified to vote] shall be entitled to have his name entered or retained in a register of electors in that year".6 The PEA further states the conditions providing for the qualification and disqualification of voters, and provides the electoral procedure. It seems clear that each citizen who qualifies under the PEA has a private statutory right to vote.

However, it is uncertain if a constitutional right to vote exists, and even if it does, the precise nature and scope of such a right remain unclear. While the Minister for Law and the Attorney-General may explicitly recognise a constitutional right to vote,7 neither office is vested with the constitutional power to make definitive pronouncements on constitutional interpretation – only the Courts may do so.8

While there seems to be judicial recognition in Vellama9 of a public constitutional right to vote,10 the pronouncement was ultimately obiter and not ratio (albeit rather strong obiter). Furthermore, the Court in Vellama did not clearly rule if citizens also have a private (i.e. personal) constitutional right to vote, one that is capable of being enforced by individual citizens who claim that their right to vote has been infringed upon by executive or legislative actions. The Court in Vellama merely suggested the existence of such a private constitutional right,11 though not making a definitive pronouncement on its existence or its scope.

Whether the private right to vote is constitutional or statutory is of monumental importance. The public right to vote is arguably satisfied as long as elections are held in accordance with the PEA. If a citizen’s private right to vote is merely statutory, it can arguably be circumvented by the legislature amending the qualification (or disqualification) provisions in the PEA12 (assuming that these amendments are not unconstitutional in some other way). However, should such a private right to vote be constitutional, a citizen would likely be able to successfully quash a legislative amendment that removes his or her ability to vote.

A citizen’s private right to vote is already significantly curtailed by the PEA. Would-be voters can be disqualified if they are accused of or serving a sentence punishable with a 12 months’ imprisonment or more,13 or if they had not voted in a previous election and had not registered to be restored to the register of electors,14 for which they have to provide a ‘good and sufficient reason’ or pay a sum of money.

Under the current status quo, it remains unclear if the right to vote is constitutionally protected, and if so, what the ‘irreducible core’ of the right to vote – that which cannot be modified or infringed upon by legislative or executive action – is. In other words, when is legislative or executive action impacting a citizen’s right to vote unconstitutional?

AN “IRREDUCIBLE CORE” OF THE RIGHT TO VOTE?

The procedural aspects of citizens’ rights to vote are detailed in the PEA, all of which are merely statutory in nature, and can be legislatively amended, unless any of these provisions are within the ‘irreducible core’ of the right to vote.15

Indeed, the PEA provides many of the conditions of the electoral process, including detailing the qualifying criteria for voters,16 providing that each voters has exactly one vote,17 and providing that the elections be held by secret ballot.18 However, as the scope of the constitutional right is still unclear, drastic changes to the PEA which significantly curtail citizens’ rights to vote (such as by increasing the voting age from 21 to 40), change the impact of voting (such as by giving some classes of citizens a larger entitlement of ballot papers), or affect each citizen’s tendencies to choose (by removing secret votes) are all prima facie constitutional. While these hypothetical amendments are politically undesirable (and Parliament can be said to be politically constrained), they can still arguably be legitimately made without any constitutional amendments. If this is truly the case, then it is arguable that the right to vote does not enjoy the “highest possible legal protection”19 in the land typically afforded to a constitutional right, unlike what the Minister for Law alluded to in his speech.20

What then, is within the ‘irreducible core’ of the right to vote? There is scant guidance from judicial or Parliamentary pronouncements, except from the rather narrow dicta in Vellama which states that the Prime Minister “cannot… [be] completely free to do as he pleases, even to the extent of delaying indefinitely the calling of a by-election”,21 although he maintains a “substantial measure of discretion”.22 This “substantial measure of discretion” may also be said to apply to the legislature seeking to amend the PEA, since it is typically afforded a “strong presumption of constitutional validity”.23

At the moment, it seems that the ‘irreducible core’ of the right to vote arguably only comprises “elections being held within a reasonable period”, and, barring exceptional circumstances, it is unlikely that a constitutional challenge of legislative or executive acts which relies on the constitutional right to vote will succeed.

THE VALUE OF AN EXPLICIT CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO VOTE

Much of the uncertainty regarding the right to vote can be remedied by inserting an express Article into the Constitution to lay out and protect the right to vote. In this regard, I disagree with the Minister for Law’s comments24 that the express recognition of this right is unnecessary as it is already well recognised as an implied right – the precise nature and scope of this right is far from clear, and should be recognised explicitly, especially given its fundamental and central nature in a democratic society. The explicit recognition of this “Super-Right”25 would also “affirm its primary importance”26 and provide it with the constitutional status and protection it deserves.


[1] Nominated Member of Parliament Prof. Thio Li-ann made a similar point in Parliament when she said: “Voting rights are the hallmark of democracy; it is the Political Right of rights, a Super-Right necessary for democracy to function authentically.” Parlimentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 85 at col 3119 (12 February 2009) (Prof. Thio Li-ann).

[2] Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 85 at col 3157 (13 February 2009) (Mr K Shanmugam).

[3] Vellama d/o Marie Muthu v Attorney-General, [2013] 4 SLR 1 [Vellama].

[4] Ibid at [79].

[5] Parliamentary Elections Act (Cap 218, 2011 Rev Ed Sing).

[6] Ibid at s 5(1).

[7] In his speech, the Minister for Law noted that he had “consulted the Attorney-General who agrees with [him] on this.” Supra note 2.

[8] Constitution of the Republic of Singapore (1999 Rev Ed), art 93.

[9] Supra note 3 at [27].

[10] A public right is one which is “shared in common with other citizens” (Vellama at [33]), and would arguably only require that elections be held (i.e. an individual cannot assert that his public right to vote is violated if an election is held, even if he is personally denied his right to vote – he would have to rely on a private or personal right).

[11] Supra note 3 at [27], [37].

[12] Supra note 5 at ss 5, 6, 7.

[13] Ibid at s 6(1A).

[14] Ibid at s 43(3).

[15] If one of the provisions within the PEA is also part of the constitutional right to vote, then a legislative amendment that purports to remove or change that provision may be unconstitutional.

[16] Supra note 5 at s 5.

[17] Ibid at s 42(1).

[18] Ibid at s 42(3).

[19] Supra note 2 at col 3158.

[20] Ibid.

[21] Supra note 3 at [78].

[22] Ibid at [87].

[23] Public Prosecutor v Taw Cheng Kong, [1998] 2 SLR (R) 489 at [60].

[24] Supra note 2.

[25] In Prof. Thio Li-ann’s words, supra note 1.

[26] Ibid.

 


Observations on the Protection of Chinese Consumer Rights in our Age of Misinformation

Download a PDF version of this entry here.


Observations on the Protection of Chinese Consumer Rights in our Age of Misinformation

Angeline Ang

I. INTRODUCTION

On April 12, 2016, 21-year-old Chinese student Wei Zexi died after a web search led him to undergo experimental treatment for cancer at a military hospital. Wei’s online account of his abysmal experience at the clinic went viral.1 The resulting media furore was largely directed at Baidu, the search engine Wei used. The majority of social media users vilified Baidu for being indirectly responsible for Wei’s death, as it had allowed the highest bidder to place advertisements for unsafe medical procedures on its site. In response, the government was quick to limit Baidu’s advertising capabilities, with the result that price is no longer the sole determinant in ranking search results (among other requirements).2 This article will evaluate the extent to which existing legal measures safeguard the rights of Chinese consumers. It will also propose solutions to protect Chinese citizens – namely, education and a relaxation of censorship laws.

II. HOW EFFECTIVELY DO CURRENT MEASURES SAFEGUARD CHINESE CONSUMER RIGHTS?

A. China's Medical Advertising Laws

Article 14 of the Advertisement Law of the People’s Republic of China [Advertisement Law] states that medical advertisements cannot include information about the medicine’s effectiveness, any unscientific assertions, or names or images of medical institutions, doctors or patients.3 Those who violate Article 14 may have to pay a fine or remove their advertisements.4 Article 34 of Advertisement Law states that advertisements for medicines and medical apparatuses shall be examined by relevant administrative departments before they are published and are prohibited from being published without examination.5 Those who publish advertisements without obtaining approval shall have to cease publication and pay a fine.6

However, given China’s suboptimal regulatory environment7 and the overwhelming number of advertisements published daily, it is clear that this provision will be of limited efficacy unless more government officials are hired to assess the suitability of advertisements. A system of checks and balances also needs to be implemented to ensure that the officials do not take bribes from advertisers.

B. China’s Consumer Protection Laws

Chinese consumers who have been harmed by deceptive advertisements may choose to sue the advertiser. Under Article 55 of the Law of Civil Procedure of the People’s Republic of China, if there are many plaintiffs who seek to file a claim against a defendant, the plaintiffs may elect representatives from among themselves to proceed with the litigation and the people’s court may issue a public notice inviting those entitled to participate in the action to register with the people’s court.8 Furthermore, the Consumer Rights Protection Law of the People’s Republic of China states that the China Consumers’ Association and authorised consumer associations shall be able to bring suit for acts which harm the legitimate interests of consumers.9 This is fairly similar to the situation in the United States where class action lawsuits often yield large settlements. Although no amount of money can undo the harm caused by shady medical products, a monetary award may ease the financial burden of those who have spent much of their life savings on such products.

The Supreme People's Court Interpretation on Several Issues Concerning the Application of Law in the Trial of Public Interest Consumer Civil Litigation Cases10 provides guidance for practitioners as to how to proceed in consumer litigation cases. However, it is equally important for such information to be communicated to the general public, to ensure that consumers are aware of the full extent of their rights. The caveat here is that many patients, particularly the lower-income and middle-class, may not be able to afford the legal fees even if they are aware of their legal rights. Furthermore, not every case will result in a hefty award of damages; this will depend on the financial status of the defendant.

C. A Loophole is Closed

After Wei’s death, a final push was made to completely end all military-provided paid public services, closing a loophole which allowed military hospitals to contract out services to private operators.11 This was the case at the cancer clinic in the military hospital where Wei underwent treatment. The hospital (the Second Hospital of Beijing Armed Police Corps) had contracted out services at its cancer clinic to a private operator which was part of the Putian-owned network of private hospitals.

The rise of the Putianese hospitals has partly been aided by the government’s underinvestment in public hospitals – over 8,000 of China’s 11,514 private hospitals are Putianese.12 Given the ubiquity of such hospitals and the fact that many are poorly run, the government should launch an investigation into the medical practices of such hospitals – revoking licenses if necessary – and accelerate its implementation of healthcare reforms. These measures would tackle the root cause of the problem of misleading advertisements more effectively than imposing restrictions on Web giants like Baidu, which can hardly be expected to possess the expertise necessary to vet healthcare advertisements. It is inevitable that some undesirable listings will slip through Baidu’s net.

That said, an investigation and healthcare reforms would undoubtedly take years and would need to be accompanied by a diminishing tendency towards corruption. For now, the new advertising rules are a timely intervention.

III. HOW SHOULD CHINA SHIELD CONSUMERS FROM THE DANGERS OF INACCURATE ADVERTISING?

Given the rise in ownership of mobile devices in China13 and increased exposure to online advertisements, it is apposite to consider other policies which could keep patients out of harm’s way. The first would be a vigorous campaign to educate consumers about the pitfalls of consuming drugs or undergoing procedures that seem too good to be true. Apart from reaching high school and university students, notices can also be disseminated at workplaces and broadcasted over television, reaching the middle-aged and elderly. Efforts should be concentrated in areas with a high density of private hospitals to maximise impact.

Patients who seek medical advice on the Internet largely do so out of desperation – as was the case with Wei and his parents – and are likely to have consulted reputable doctors before pursuing other options. It would thus be helpful if the medical profession were to be more vigilant in warning patients about the dangers of seeking medical treatment via unregulated means before patients are inclined to do so. Netizens’ comments in the aftermath of the Baidu saga show that many have high expectations of the advertisements they see in print and non-print media. A sustained counter-advertising campaign by the government could go a long way towards tempering such expectations. In the long term, education will have the added benefit of inculcating a sense of personal responsibility among Chinese consumers, ensuring that they thoroughly research medical products before purchase. Secondly, a relaxation of Chinese Internet censorship policies – known colloquially as the ‘Great Firewall of China’ – would enable consumers to undertake comprehensive research on various medical procedures and products. Currently, websites like Google and The New York Times are banned in China and Baidu has virtually monopolised the sphere of online advertising, severely limiting netizens’ options. As Wei himself noted in his online post, he had to rely on a Chinese friend in the US to use Google to search for information on his treatment after the treatment failed. It was only then that he discovered that “American hospitals had long stopped using the technology due to poor results in clinical trials”. In Wei’s case, access to Google prior to undergoing treatment may very well have saved his life.

While it is possible to bypass the Internet censorship, it would be patently unfair if the Internet savvy alone were able to access basic healthcare information. (It is worth noting that Wei himself was a computer science student, yet he had to rely on a friend in the US to use Google.) Wide swathes of the population would be left vulnerable to the predatory practices of unscrupulous private operators. China’s political motives for Internet censorship should not automatically preclude the possibility of making the ‘Great Firewall of China’ more porous and allowing users to access a greater variety of websites. Consumers who are better informed are far less likely to undergo unsafe medical procedures. This would alleviate the burden on China’s burgeoning healthcare system and improve China’s international image.

IV. CONCLUSION

Wei’s death led many to blame Baidu for its ‘evil’ practice of allowing healthcare providers to pay large sum for highly-ranked advertisements on its site. It is arguable that some of this blame is misplaced as the root cause of the problem lies in China’s draconian censorship practices, its underfunded healthcare system and the private operators which have crept in to fill the vacuum. As with any complex issue, there are no quick or easy answers. Only time will tell whether the Chinese authorities will be able to muster the political will and resources to ensure that their countrymen are able to avoid a fate like Wei’s.


[1] Paul Carsten, “China curbs Baidu healthcare ads business after student's death”, Reuters (May 9 2016) online: Reuters <http://www.reuters.com/article/us-baidu-regulations-idUSKCN0Y014U>.

[2] Ibid.

[3] Advertisement Law of the People's Republic of China, 1994, Art 14.

[4] Ibid, Art 41.

[5] Supra note 3 at Art 34.

[6] Supra note 3 at Art 43.

[7] E.g. the 2008 tainted-milk scandal or the recent discovery of sales of millions of illegal vaccines: Megha Rajagopalan, “China bars vaccine sales by drug wholesalers after scandal: state media”, Reuters (April 26 2016) online: Reuters <http://www.reuters.com/article/us-china-drugs-vaccines-idUSKCN0XM1FV>.

[8] Law of Civil Procedure of the People’s Republic of China, 1991, Art 55.

[9] National People’s Congress of the People’s Republic of China, Decision of the Standing Committee of the National People’s Congress on Revision of the Consumer Rights Protection Law of the People’s Republic of China as promulgated on October 23, 2013, effective March 15, 2014, Art 47.

[10] Legal Interpretation [2016], No 10.

[11] Ding Xuezhen, “Military leadership meets to hash out end to paid services”, Global Times (May 9 2016) online: Global times < http://www.globaltimes.cn/content/982007.shtml>. 

[12] Kou Jie, “Military cancer clinic deal under scrutiny”, Global Times (4 May 2016) online: Global Times < http://www.globaltimes.cn/content/981236.shtml>.

[13] Jacob Poushter, “Smartphone Ownership and Internet Usage Continues to Climb in Emerging Economies”, Pew Research Center (July 25 2016) online: Pew Global <http://www.pewglobal.org/2016/02/22/smartphone-ownership-and-internet-usage-continues-to-climb-in-emerging-economies/>


Justice Steven Chong delivers 28th Singapore Law Review Annual Lecture

Justice Steven Chong delivers 28th Singapore Law Review Annual Lecture

On the 8th of November 2016, the Honourable Justice Steven Chong delivered the 28th Singapore Law Review Annual Lecture, titled “Recalibration of the Death Penalty: Origin, Ramifications and Impact”. The Lecture focused on the amendments to the mandatory death penalty scheme under the Misuse of Drugs Act and the Penal Code, both of which were amended in 2012.

Dead in the Water: The Nautical Fault Exemption of the Hague-Visby Rules

Download the PDF version of this entry here.


Dead in the Water: The Nautical Fault Exemption of the Hague-Visby Rules

Phoebe Leau

The Hague-Visby Rules (“HVR”), devised nearly a century ago, are an anachronism. Today, they precede at least two other treaties1 which were contrived with the intention to modernise existing laws on maritime carriage.2 No doubt the HVR are a wellspring of academic controversy – they have been ruthlessly branded as “outdated”3 and nonsensical.4 The opprobrium is not wholly unjust: the modern phenomenon of containerisation (affreightment of goods by container), for instance, makes a complete farce5 out of the HVR’s exclusion of on-deck cargo.6

This essay addresses, in particular, Art IV(2)(a), which encapsulates the nautical fault exemption (“NFE”). The NFE immunises carriers from liability for loss or damage in consequence of any “act, neglect, or default of the master … or [its] servants … in the navigation or … management of the ship.” Broadly, it is theorised that the NFE has long outlived its utility. Its continued preservation therefore jeopardises cargo interests.

I. IS THE NFE AN ARTEFACT OF THE PAST?

Before the genesis of the NFE, carriers bore strict liability7 for all damage to cargo interests despite less-sophisticated tools of communications preventing them from managing the ship or its crew during voyage.8 Increasingly, carriers resorted to contractual exemption clauses to relieve themselves of extensive liability,9 to the detriment of cargo interests. The HVR was thus a legal mechanism by which the law attempted to strike a delicate balance between carrier and cargo interests: it establishes an ‘irreducible core’ of carrier obligations, but allows carriers to escape liability in exceptional circumstances,10 such as where carriers experience nautical fault.

At first blush, the NFE seems defensible. It serves as an apportionment of risks between cargo and carrier interests, such that the latter will not bear the full brunt of liability for crew, cargo, and vessel in a collision.11 Additionally, since carriers tend not to be involved in the carriage of goods once the vessel departs from the port of loading, exonerating carriers from responsibility for the actions of those actually involved in the carriage is ostensibly fair.

The above, however, erroneously assumes that carriers remain incapable of controlling the vessel whilst it traverses the high seas today. In reality, it is evident that technological revolution renders the NFE otiose. Contemporary satellite technologies, for instance, enable continuous monitoring and control of ship operations (including the actions of the ship’s crew) through, inter alia, radar and GPS.12 Carriers have also been held to comparatively higher standards of vessel management.13 Technology has rectified the very problem the NFE sought to alleviate – that a shore-based carrier loses control of the vessel upon its departure from the port.14 It also diminished the enormity of risks borne by carriers during the period of carriage, as increased control of the ship generally reduces risks of mischief and risks to cargo, crew or vessel.

In principle, risks should be borne by the party who is in a better position to obviate such loss.15 Against contemporary developments, the carrier, who is actually able to supervise the cargo while it remains at sea (through, inter alia, improved maritime technology or appointing competent mariners), is thus better poised to assume the risk of cargo damage. However, the NFE continues to foist upon cargo interests the burden of such risks, even though cargo owners can do effectively nothing to minimise or eliminate risks while the goods are in transit. It follows that, firstly, the NFE is excessively rigid and fails to accommodate changes to maritime practices; secondly, that risk allocation under the NFE is manifestly prejudicial to cargo interests, especially when one considers the broad range of actions (any “acts, neglect, or default”) contemplated by the provision.

II. OTHER SALIENT CRITICISMS

The NFE has been described as “conceptually awkward”, as it enables carriers to benefit from proving the negligence of shipboard personnel16 who are typically its agents17 and/or employees. This is arguably an aberration: the party which has access to how the loss occurred is ordinarily not required to show the fault of others, but rather that such loss occurred independently of its own fault.18 The NFE also defies time-tested legal doctrines such as vicarious liability19 (of the carrier through the errant mariner), and it is not altogether clear why the shipping context should be the exception to the norm.20

Separately, the dissonance between the HVR and other international conventions for carriage of goods is conspicuous. The Hamburg Rules and the Rotterdam Rules have all expunged the NFE.21 Moreover, no equivalent of the NFE exists in treaties governing carriage by road,22 rail,23 and air24 – where carriers are prima facie liable until they prove the converse.25 Significantly, the Warsaw Convention governing aviation transport was drafted in the same time period as the HVR; the defence of negligent navigation of the aircraft was, however, eliminated by the Hague Protocol of 1955. This absence of the NFE from these treaties per se underpins the fact that the Art IV(2)(a) is plainly antiquated.

III. IS THE NFE BEYOND SALVATION?

In practice, Courts are loath to interpret the NFE too liberally,26 being very much alive to its notoriety. Judicial discretion in construction is thus exercised to limit the applicability of the NFE. The question is whether such discretion as exercised is capable of salvaging the inherent deficiencies in Art IV(2)(a). While acknowledging that ‘reading down’ the NFE can impede the force and frequency with which the NFE is applied, this writer contends that it is not.

As a preliminary note, Art IV(2)(a) governs all “[acts], neglect, or default”, and is not accompanied by any ‘qualification’ clause27 specifying acts which fall outside the provision. By necessary implication, Art IV(2)(a) would exempt liability for wilful, intentional or reckless conduct.28 The all-encompassing scope of Art IV(2)(a) is somewhat alarming. However, even if it does exclude intentional transgressions,29 its ambit remains unduly expansive. This is immediately apparent from The Tasman Pioneer,30 in which the Court opined that the NFE is only inapplicable to “damage with actual or imputed intent”, as envisaged in Art IVbis(4).31 It was further clarified that a carrier need not prove the bona fides of persons enumerated in the provision to avail himself of protection conferred by the NFE.32 On the facts, the master conducted himself disingenuously in pursuance of personal benefit, but not an intention to cause harm.33 Absent the latter, the carrier could not be liable for the master’s mala fides – which include, inter alia, the falsification of the vessel’s course plot post-collision and attempted concealment.

Respectfully, the ruling in The Tasman Pioneer bodes ill for cargo interests. It is not disputed that masters are agents of the shipowner and, that under agency law, principals are not invariably liable for the deeds of its agent. However, this case signifies that cargo interests have effectively no recourse against the wrongdoings of shipboard personnel, unless they can show that the carrier’s agents or servants acted with actual or imputed intention to cause damage.34 From the perspective of cargo interests, this is a nearly insurmountable evidentiary barrier. How can cargo owners, who are not usually privy to ship management and navigation at sea, be realistically expected to meet their burden of proof? In any case, there is no logical reason why a carrier should be liable for its servant’s barratry, but escape liability for other morally objectionable conduct of a lesser degree than barratry. The generosity with which carriers are treated therefore engenders tremendous injustice for cargo interests.

Apart from interpreting the term “acts”, the NFE may also be circumscribed by manipulating the terms “navigation” and “management of the ship”. It is well-established that “navigation” entails seamanship35 and includes steering the wrong course.36 In Gosse Millerd v Canadian Government Merchant Marine, Greer LJ (whose dissent the House of Lords endorsed on appeal) held that an alleged act will constitute ship management if it relates primarily to the care of the ship. However, if it relates solely or primarily to the cargo, it will not be an act of ship management.37

The differentiation of cargo management from ship management is contentious – not least because such distinction can often be tenuous. In The Iron Gippsland38 and The Eternity39 respectively, the negligent operation of a gas tanker (designated for vessel protection) and a ship’s valve both amounted to cargo mismanagement, which fell beyond the ambit of the NFE. In contradistinction, the failure to secure tarpaulins to the ship’s hatches was construed as an act of ship management in The Hector,40 as the structure in its entirety formed part of the ship’s defences.41

It is acknowledged, however, that subsequent decisions have cast doubt on The Hector and its instructiveness is suspect. Additionally, this writer observes that it is now more difficult for a carrier to invoke the NFE:42 in the later cases, courts have engaged in robust scrutiny of alleged acts of ship mismanagement to better safeguard cargo interests.43 The corollary is that judicial discretion exercised in interpretation of Art IV(2)(a) aids in achieving an optimal balance of interests between the two camps. However, the very existence of a need to ‘read down’ the NFE highlights the sheer breadth of immunity granted under the provision, as well as its fundamental incompetence in coping with changing attitudes.

It bears mention that the distinction between ship and cargo management is susceptible to obfuscation by the involvement of containerised cargo. Containers can serve as the ship’s apparatus/equipment if supplied by the carrier,44 or be construed as an extension of the ship’s superstructure.45 Hence, there may be difficulties in discerning when, for example, the mishandling of containerised cargo during voyage might equate to a breach of Art III(2), or mismanagement of the ship as conceived by Art IV(2)(a) – each of which will produce vastly dissimilar consequences. If it falls within the latter category, the carrier is immune from liability irrespective of any breach of Art III(2).46 This may result in the frustration of legitimate expectations of cargo interests, and is arguably unfair.

Where the NFE does apply, courts can do little to mitigate the hefty losses suffered by cargo interests. This is because Art IV(2)(a), in exempting liability for all loss and damage, can supersede breaches of other obligations in the HVR. In The Aconcagua,47 the heating of a bunker tank caused the ignition of a cargo of dangerous chemicals; subsequently, an explosion transpired. Notwithstanding that the charterers failed to properly care for the cargo,48 the Court found that they were protected by the NFE, as the heating of the bunker tank (for transfer to the engine room) constituted ship management.49 This decision, if anything, epitomises the injustice to cargo interests perpetuated by the NFE. The charterers could not have escaped liability for contravening their obligations under Art III(2) but for the existence of Art IV(2)(a).50 However, their liability under Art III(2) was ultimately subordinated to the NFE.

IV. CONCLUSION

Ironically, the very progenitor of the NFE — the U.S., by s 3 of the Harter Act51 — has since pressed for its deletion in Senate proposals for its new Carriage of Goods by Sea Act52 and the travaux préparatoires to the Rotterdam Rules.53 If anything, this demonstrates that the NFE is in a state of obsolescence. The rigid insistence of Art IV(2)(a) on risk allocation in favour of carrier interests, for instance, accentuates the incapability of the NFE to adapt to contemporary developments in maritime carriage. Yet, this is to be expected when one ruminates upon the historical background of the HVR: its drafting and negotiations process was dominated by powerful ship-owning economies, which resulted in the over-representation of carrier interests. Additionally, the focus on ‘codifying’ industry practices as they stood rendered the HVR’s provisions overly specific and unpliable, leaving no room for the incorporation of subsequent transformations and changes.

In light of the shortcomings of the NFE, its deletion and substitution with ‘prima facie’ fault provisions in the Hamburg Rules and Rotterdam Rules is emphatically welcome. It may be that, very exceptionally, the allocation of risks under the NFE creates a fair compromise between cargo and carrier interests. This might be so in cases where, for example, the shipowner was unable to exert control over the vessel (perhaps due to breakdown in telecommunications).55 Also, the deletion of the NFE may well increase the risks borne by carriers and cause a corresponding spike in freight rates.56 Ultimately, however, it bears emphasis that cargo interests are in a more vulnerable and precarious position than carriers, for reasons highlighted above. Carriers should therefore bear higher risks than cargo owners while goods are in transit, so that the interests of both parties can be evenly balanced. The HVR falter in this respect, thus offering a disappointing compromise on cargo interests.


[1] Hamburg Rules (1978); Rotterdam Rules (2008).

[2] E.g. Preamble of Rotterdam Rules.

[3] Myburgh, “Uniformity or Unilateralism in the Law of Carriage of Goods by Sea?” (2000) 31 VUWLR 355, 367.

[4] A New International Regime for Carriage of Goods by Sea (2012) 30 BJIL. 303, 320.

[5] Ibid.

[6] Art 1 (c).

[7] Liang & Li, “Abolishing the Exemption of Liability for Fault in Ship Management in the Nautical Fault Exemption System” (2006) China Oceans L.R. 537 at 542, 539.

[8] Supra note 4, 329.

[9] Gosse Millerd Ltd v Canadian Government Merchant Marine Ltd [1929] AC 223, 236

[10] As enumerated in Art IV(2).

[11] Weitz, “The Nautical Fault Debate” (1997-1998) 22 TMLJ 581, 588.

[12] Supra note 11, 594.

[13] See e.g. International Convention on Standards of Training, Certification and Watchkeeping for Seafarers.

[14] Zeigler, “Liability of the Contracting Carrier” (2008-2009) 44 TILJ 329, 342.

[15] Supra note 11, 587.

[16] Ibid.

[17] E.g. Masters: Girvin, Carriage of Goods by Sea (Oxford: OUP, 2011), [1.40].

[18] Supra note 11.

[19] Faria, “New Times, New Players, and New Rules” (2008-2009) 44 TILJ 277, 299.

[20] Allocating Shipment Risks (1978) 4 Monash U.L.R. 117, 149.

[21] Supra note 7, 542.

[22] 1956 Convention on the Contract for the International Carriage of Goods by Road.

[23] 1980 Convention concerning International Carriage by Rail.

[24] 1933 Warsaw Convention.

[25] Supra note 11.

[26] Clarke, Maritime Law Evolving (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2013), 143.

[27] See e.g. Art IV(5)(e) .

[28] Treitel, Carver on Bills of Lading (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 2005), 607.

[29] Which may well be the case in light of Art IVbis(4) read with Art IVbis(1).

[30] [2010] NZSC 37.

[31] Ibid, [13].

[32] Ibid, [21].

[33] Supra note 30, [34].

[34] Supra note 30.

[35] The Hill Harmony [2001] 1 Lloyd’s Rep 147, 159.

[36]  The Satya Kailash & Oceanic Amity [1982] 2 Lloyd’s Rep 465.

[37] [1928] 1 KB 717, 749.

[38] [1994] 1 Lloyd’s Rep 335, 358.

[39] [2009] 1 Lloyd’s Rep 107.

[40] [1955] 2 Lloyd’s Rep 218.

[41] Ibid, 234-235.

[42] Supra note 19.

[43] Cooke et al, Voyage Charters (Oxon: Routledge, 2014), [85.279].

[44] In Houlden & Co v. S.S. Red Jacket [1978] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 300, the Court held that the standard of seaworthiness applied to “all of the ship’s equipment, including containers supplied to the shippers” (at 1401).

[45] Aladwani, “The Supply of Containers & Seaworthiness” (2011) 42 JMLC 185, 188.

[46] Art III(2) is “subject to the provisions of Art IV”.

[47] [2009] EWHC 1880.

[48] Ibid, [371].

[49] Ibid, [372].

[50] Hashmi, “Rotterdam Rules: A Blessing?” (2011-2012) 10 Loyola MLJ 227, 247.

[51] Harter Act of 1893, 46 U.S.C. §190-196.

[52] Supra note 26.

[53] UN Doc. A/CN.9/WG.III/WP.34 at [30].

[54] Sweeney, “UNCITRAL and the Hague Rules” (1991) 22 JMLC 511, 516.

[55] Mandelbaum, “Risk Allocation for Cargo Loss, Damage, and Delay” (1995-1996) 5 JTLP 1, 38.

[56] Supra note 19.


Dialogue with Minister for Law on proposed changes to the Elected Presidency

Dialogue with Minister for Law on proposed changes to the Elected Presidency

On the 13th of October, 2016, the Singapore Law Review hosted Minister for Home Affairs and Minister for Law, Mr K Shanmugam, for an intimate dialogue session with law students to discuss proposed changes to the Elected Presidency. The dialogue session came just three days after a Bill to formally introduce these proposed changes into the Constitution of Singapore was tabled in Parliament.

The Disclosure of Medical Risks in Singapore and the case of Montgomery

Download the PDF version of this entry here.


The Disclosure of Medical Risks in Singapore and the case of Montgomery

Keith Jieren Thirumaran

INTRODUCTION

There are three main areas that doctors engage in when practicing medicine: diagnosis, treatment and advice. In order for doctors to avoid negligence liability, they must meet the applicable standard of care expected of them. However, in the context of advice with respect to disclosure of risks, the test for determining whether a doctor is in breach of the applicable standard of care has attracted a considerable amount of attention. Singapore has retained the traditional doctor-centric test, but several overseas jurisdictions have since developed more patient-focused approaches – notably, the recent UK Supreme Court decision of Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board [Montgomery].1 This article will examine the various tests used by courts both locally and overseas, after which it will be submitted that the status quo in Singapore should be maintained in light of compelling local circumstances.

TESTS USED LOCALLY AND OVERSEAS

The Singapore position pre-Montgomery

The current position in Singapore is embodied in the Court of Appeal case of Dr Khoo James & Anor v Gunapathy d/o Muniandy [Gunapathy]2 where the Court applied the Bolam-Bolitho test to the disclosure of risks in the medical context.

The Bolam-Bolitho test is the locus classicus for the standard of care required of doctors and comprises of two separate tests. The plaintiff must show that a doctor defendant has failed either of these tests in order to establish a breach of the standard of care.

The Bolam test, formulated in Bolam v Friern Hospital Management Committee,3 requires a doctor to have acted in accordance with a practice accepted as proper by a responsible body of medical men skilled in that particular art. This means that a doctor will not be found negligent as long as part of the medical profession agrees with what the doctor did, even if there is a body of opinion that takes the contrary view,4 and even if the court prefers one of the views over the other.5

The Bolitho test, formulated in Bolitho v City & Hackney Health Authority,6 is a threshold test of logic and consistency when accepting the opinion of medical peers. This comprises two stages: the expert must have directed his mind to the comparative risks and benefits of the matter; and the opinion must be a defensible conclusion, meaning that it must be internally consistent and should not ignore known medical facts.7

The main reasons the Court of Appeal in Gunapathy cited for applying the Bolam-Bolitho test was that judicial wisdom has its limits. A judge unskilled in medicine has no business adjudicating matters which medical experts themselves cannot agree on.8 Furthermore, excessive judicial interference would hamper the proper development of medical science, give rise to defensive medicine, and lead to higher medical costs and wastage of medical resources. 9

The development of the “prudent patient” approach

In the UK case of Sidaway v Bethlem Royal Hospital Governors [Sidaway],10 Lord Scarman in his dissent suggested moving from the Bolam-Bolitho approach toward a “prudent patient” test similar to that found in the American case of Canterbury v Spence.11 In the Australian case of Rogers v Whitaker [Rogers],12 the High Court favoured Lord Scarman’s dissent13 and decided the case on the basis of what risks a “prudent patient” would wish to know, save for the exception of therapeutic privilege cases. The Canadian Supreme Court case of Reibl v Hughes14 and the Malaysian Federal Court case of Foo Fio Na v Dr Soo Fook Mun & Anor15 have also taken similar approaches to the disclosure of risks in the medical context.

In the UK itself, the majority decision in Sidaway is no longer good law. The case has since been effectively overruled by the recent Supreme Court decision of Montgomery.16 The Montgomery approach17 is that a doctor must disclose risks that a reasonable person in the patient’s position would attach significance to, as well as risks that the doctor should reasonably be aware that the actual patient would attach significance to. The patient need not question the doctor,18 though the doctor must engage in a proper dialogue with the patient to ensure that the latter is aware of and understands the risks.19

There are three exceptions to the above test where a doctor does not have to disclose the relevant risks.20 The first is when the patient does not wish to know any further information.21 The second is the therapeutic privilege exception which allows a doctor to withhold information from the patient if the doctor reasonably considers that its disclosure would be seriously detrimental to the patient’s health. 22. The third is in circumstances of necessity such as when treatment is required urgently but the patient is unconscious or otherwise unable to make a decision.23

Whether the risk is considered material enough to be disclosed depends on various factors such as magnitude of risk, nature of risk, effect of its occurrence upon the life of the patient, importance to patient of the benefits from treatment, alternative treatments and risks of those alternative treatments (“Montgomery Factors”).24

Singapore’s stance on the “prudent patient approach”

Although the Singapore High Court acknowledged Montgomery in the cases of Thong Jiang Andrew v Yue Wai Mun & Anor 25 and Hii Chii Kok v Ooi Peng Jin London Lucien and another,26 it left the question of which test should apply open (Bolam-Bolitho or Montgomery). Nonetheless, on the existing facts, it seems that the Singapore Courts favour the Bolam-Bolitho test.

Firstly, the Court of Appeal in Gunapathy, in the context of advice and disclosure of risks, did not find favour with Lord Scarman’s dissent in Sidaway, the foundations for the prudent patient approach as discussed above. Instead, the Court in Gunapathy preferred to follow the majority in Sidaway in applying the Bolam-Bolitho test to the context of advice and disclosure of risks.27

Secondly, the Court in Gunapathy also noted that Lord Bridge’s qualification in Sidaway (that if there was a substantial risk and no cogent clinical reason for non-disclosure, a Judge can conclude that no respectable medical expert would have failed to disclose that risk) was already subsumed under the Bolitho test and was therefore unnecessary.28

Thirdly, Chief Justice Sundaresh Menon, in his address at the Opening of the Legal Year 2016, has also emphasised the importance of preventing doctors from practicing defensive medicine.29 The Learned Chief Justice also promoted the use of alternative dispute resolution such as mediation, as opposed to litigation, for resolving medical disputes.30 This is further evidence of the importance of reducing medical litigation in Singapore, which is more in line with the Bolam-Bolitho test. The Montgomery test, on the other hand, may subject doctors to greater legal liability.

COMMENTARY ON THE FUTURE POSITION IN SINGAPORE

Since the position in the UK (which Singapore was following) has been changed by the case of Montgomery, the Singapore Court of Appeal will have to consider this and other international developments to determine which test should apply in Singapore. While some may be quick to cast their vote for a change to Montgomery, this author believes that Singapore should stick to its current position and uphold the Bolam-Bolitho test.

Underlying policy considerations in support of the Bolam-Bolitho test

Policy reasons form the basis for sticking to the Bolam-Bolitho test, in particular, hampering the proper development of medical science, giving rise to defensive medicine, higher medical costs and wastage of medical resources.31 As Chief Justice Menon pointed out in his address, a fear of litigation would distort medical practice and raise insurance costs.32 These are fundamental policy considerations that underpin the Bolam-Bolitho test and they are still as strong today.

At first glance, it would appear that the learned Chief Justice’s concerns were already considered by the Supreme Court in Montgomery. The Supreme Court in that case disagreed that there was a possibility of increased litigation and defensive medicine from its approach. Furthermore, the Court opined that its approach would result in patients being aware that the outcome of treatment is uncertain, and that its approach allows patients to take responsibility for the ultimate choice of undergoing that treatment.33 This, in the Court’s opinion, would therefore lower the likelihood of litigation in the event of an adverse outcome.34

However, this author respectfully disagrees with the views expressed in Montgomery. While it may be thought that less litigation would directly translate into less defensive practices, this is not necessarily true. The very fact that doctors under the Montgomery approach have to disclose more risks is itself a defensive practice which would lead to higher costs. Doctors would never be sure where to draw the line, and would “play safe” by disclosing many, if not all, the risks associated with the treatment.

In Montgomery, the Court failed to take into account the increased medical costs involved with their approach.35 The defensive medical practice of disclosing more risks of treatment (in order to avoid liability for failing to disclose a risk) would lead to “higher medical costs and wastage of precious medical resources”.36 More time will be needed to disclose and explain risks, which could have been spent treating another person or saving a life (which the Court in Montgomery did not discuss). Time wastage may be exacerbated where a patient who has been notified of many new risks is inclined to further question the doctor for explanations, elaborations, and evaluations on them, regardless of the significance of the risk. The Montgomery approach may raise medical costs, going against the aims that the learned Chief Justice and the Court in Gunapathy had sought to achieve.

Furthermore, even with the therapeutic privilege exception, disclosing every conceivable risk to a patient that is not “at-risk” can still cause unbalanced decisions and frighten the patient.37 A patient may opt for a more expensive treatment or refuse otherwise viable treatment when frightened by an insignificant risk. It is therefore submitted that in order to avoid higher medical costs and wastage of resources, the decision of which risks are significant enough to the patient and need to be disclosed should best be left to the judgment of the medical profession.

Lastly, the Court in Montgomery felt that imposing legal obligations was necessary to force doctors to engage in a discussion with their patients. However, as Baroness Hale said in Gregg v Scott,38 doctors are motivated by their natural desire and professional duty to do their best for their patients. It is this author’s opinion that a doctor would therefore engage in the discussion with their patients, even without legal obligations, as long as the doctor feels that it would be in the patient’s interest to know of a particular risk.

Montgomery’s human rights focus is inapplicable to Singapore

The decisions in the UK, such as Montgomery, may not be applicable in Singapore. This is because, as stated by the Singapore High Court, the UK decisions may have been influenced by the UK’s emphasis on human rights and autonomy.39 This emphasis on human rights and autonomy in the UK may be attributed to the European Convention of Human Rights [ECHR],40 enforced under the Human Rights Act [HRA].41

However, neither the ECHR nor the HRA is binding on Singapore Courts.42 Therefore, in the absence of any rights-based legislation, the Singapore Courts may not be inclined to adopt an approach, such as Montgomery, which is based on a strong emphasis of Human Rights.43

Bolam-Bolitho and Montgomery tests likely to reach the same conclusion

The Bolam-Bolitho test would, in this author’s opinion, already encompass the bulk of the Montgomery approach. It is submitted that the large majority of risks disclosed under the Montgomery approach would already be disclosed under the Bolam-Bolitho test, ultimately giving rise to same legal conclusions.

Firstly, if a doctor is aware that his patient would attach significance to a particular risk, then in the absence of cogent medical reasons such as the therapeutic privilege exception, there appears to be no reason why that doctor would not disclose that risk to the patient. Therefore, it appears that any reasonable doctor would disclose risks that he is aware his patient finds significant, thereby satisfying the Bolam test, while also satisfying the Montgomery test.

Secondly, even in the absence of any cognisance of specific significance to his patient, a doctor would disclose risks that the doctor believes should be disclosed. A doctor is likely to take into account the various Montgomery Factors listed above (save for “importance to patient of the benefits from treatment”) when making an assessment of what to disclose to a patient. Therefore, save for the internal thoughts of a patient, a reasonably doctor who satisfies the Bolam test by considering the Montgomery Factors would satisfy the Montgomery test and disclose all material risks.

Furthermore, in Singapore the minimum that the Bolam test requires a reasonable doctor to do would be to adhere to the Singapore Medical Council’s Ethical Code and Ethical Guidelines [Ethical Code].44 The Ethical Code requires doctors to keep a patient “adequately informed” of his treatment options so that “he is able to participate in decisions about his treatment”.45 The Ethical Code also requires doctors to “provide adequate information” so that a patient can make “informed choices”.46 As the wording is notably broad, it is highly probable that a doctor which satisfies the provision of “adequate information” under the Bolam test is likely to have disclosed all material risks and thereby satisfy the Montgomery test.

Thirdly, there is no risk of the medical profession exploiting the Bolam-Bolitho test. This is because if the responsible body of medical men would not have disclosed the risk, and if this is not founded on a logical basis, the Bolitho test would then step in.47 The Bolitho test is not an invasive inquiry into the merits of the medical opinion before the Court.48 However, if the medical profession illogically omits to warn of certain risks which patients should undoubtedly be informed of, the Court should interfere on the authority of Bolitho.49 This is especially so when the disclosure of that particular risk was so obviously necessary in order for the patient to make an informed choice.50 An example provided by the Court was if the risk is substantial, of grave consequences and there is no cogent clinical reason for omitting to disclose the risk.51 Therefore the Bolitho test will help to catch risks that should be disclosed under Montgomery but where the medical profession as a whole would not have done so.

The Montgomery test is impractical

Even with the practical similarities highlighted above, it is acknowledged there are a handful of risks that a prudent patient would want disclosed that a reasonable body of medical men would not have disclosed. This handful of risks would be caught by the Montgomery approach but would not have been caught under the Bolam-Bolitho test. The existence of these risks stem from the main difference between the Bolam-Bolitho test and the Montgomery approach: the perspective from which the test is applied.

It is submitted that the Montgomery test provides a very artificial guideline to follow and it would not be realistic to expect a doctor to adhere to such a test. While it is acknowledged that a doctor can attempt to think from the perspective of a reasonable patient, and thereby theoretically be able to cover some of the material risks from a patient’s perspective, the reality is that a doctor cannot tell with any precision or certainty what a reasonable patient would wish to know. Therefore, in their bid to escape liability under the Montgomery test, a doctor would practice defensive medicine by simply disclosing every conceivable risk. This is undesirable as it would lead to the aforementioned higher medical costs and wastage of medical resources.

Therefore, applying the Montgomery approach only gives the appearance of human rights and autonomy. Instead, the Montgomery approach would lead to more prevalent defensive practices as well as unnecessarily cause a greater number of doctors to be found negligent merely due to the unrealistic expectation of predicting what a prudent patient would want to know.

CONCLUSION

In conclusion, the Singapore Courts should not feel pressured to accept the approaches adopted in other jurisdictions but should choose the approach that is most desirable to the Singapore context and society. It may well be that maintaining the status quo could be the better approach for Singapore.


[1] Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board, [2015] UKSC 11.

[2] Dr Khoo James & Anor v Gunapathy d/o Muniandy, [2002] 2 SLR 414.

[3] Bolam v Friern Hospital Management Committee, [1957] 1 WLR 582 at 587.

[4] Ibid.

[5] Maynard v West Midlands Regional Health Authority, [1985] 1 All ER 635.

[6] Bolitho v City & Hackney Health Authority, [1998] AC 232 at 241-242.

[7] Supra note 2 at [64] – [65].

[8] Supra note 2 at [144].

[9] Ibid.

[10] Sidaway v Bethlem Royal Hospital Governors, [1985] AC 871.

[11] Canterbury v Spence, (1972) 464 F 2d 772.

[12] Rogers v Whitaker, (1992) 175 CLR 479.

[13] Ibid at [10].

[14] Reibl v Hughes, (1980) 114 DLR (3d).

[15] Foo Fio Na v Dr Soo Fook Mun & Anor, [2007] 1 MLJ 593.

[16] Supra note 1.

[17] Supra note 1 at [87].

[18] Supra note 1at [58].

[19] Supra note 1 at [90].

[20] Supra note 1 at [85] and [88].

[21] Supra note 1 at [85].

[22] Supra note 1 at [88].

[23] Supra note 1 at [88].

[24] Supra note 1 at [89].

[25] Thong Jiang Andrew v Yue Wai Mun & Anor, [2015] SGHC 119 at [36] – [37].

[26] Hii Chii Kok v Ooi Peng Jin London Lucien and another, [2016] SGHC 21.

[27] Supra note 2 at [142].

[28] Supra note 2 at [141].

[29] Chief Justice Sundaresh Menon: Response at the Opening of the Legal Year 2016 (11 January 2016), online: <http://www.supremecourt.gov.sg/Data/Editor/Documents/Response%20by%
20CJ%20%20Opening%20of%20the%20Legal%20Year%202016%20on%2011%20January%202016%20(Checked%20against%20Delivery%20110116).pdf> at [43].

[30] Ibid.

[31] Supra note 2 at [144].

[32] Ibid.

[33] Supra note 1 at [93].

[34] Ibid.

[35] It is suggested that the UK’s National Health Service may have been a contributing factor that would have downplayed the concern of patients’ medical costs for the Court in Montgomery.

[36] Supra note 2 at [144].

[37] Tong Seok May Joanne v Yau Hok Man Gordon, [2012] SGHC 252 at [76].

[38] Gregg v Scott [2005] UKHL 2 at [217].

[39] D’Conceicao Jeanie Doris (administratrix of the estate of Milakov Steven, deceased) v Tong Ming Chuan [D’Conceicao], [2011] SGHC 193 at [123]; Tong Seok May Joanne v Yau Hok Man Gordon [2012] SGHC 252 at [64] and [172].

[40] Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 4 November 1950, 213 UNTS 221 (entered into force 3 September 1953)

[41] Human Rights Act 1998 (UK), c 42.

[42] Supra note 38.

[43] Ibid.

[44] Singapore Medical Council, Ethical Code and Ethical Guidelines, online: <http://www.healthprofessionals.gov.sg/content/dam/hprof/smc/docs/guidelines/SMC%20Ethical%20Code%20and%20Ethical%20Guidelines.pdf>.

[45] Ibid at 4.2.2.

[46] Ibid at 4.2.4.

[47] Supra note 2 at [141].

[48] D’Conceicao at [40].

[49] Ibid at [124].

[50] Supra note 10 at 900.

[51] Ibid.